Click here and press the right key for the next slide.
(This may not work on mobile or ipad. You can try using chrome or firefox, but even that may fail. Sorry.)
also ...
Press the left key to go backwards (or swipe right)
Press n to toggle whether notes are shown (or add '?notes' to the url before the #)
Press m or double tap to slide thumbnails (menu)
Press ? at any time to show the keyboard shortcuts
1. Ethical judgements are explained by a dual-process theory, which distinguishes faster from slower processes.
2. Faster processes are unreliable in unfamiliar* situations.
3. Therefore, we should not rely on faster process in unfamiliar* situations.
4. When philosophers rely on not-justified-inferentially premises, they are relying on faster processes.
5. We have reason to suspect that the moral scenarios and principles philosophers consider are unfamiliar situations.
6. Therefore, not-justified-inferentially premises about particular moral scenarios, and debatable principles, cannot be used in ethical arguments where the aim is knowledge.
‘genetic transmission, cultural transmission, and learning from personal experience [...] are the only mechanisms known to endow [fast] processes with the information they need to function well’
Greene 2014, p. 714
unfamiliar* problems = ‘ones with which we have inadequate evolutionary, cultural, or personal experience’
‘it would be a cognitive miracle if we had reliably good moral instincts about unfamiliar* moral problems’
‘The No Cognitive Miracles Principle:
When we are dealing with unfamiliar* moral problems, we ought to rely less on [...] automatic emotional responses and more on [...] conscious, controlled reasoning, lest we bank on cognitive miracles.’
Greene, 2014 p. 715
Is how to win a chess match an unfamiliar problem?
unfamiliar* problems = ‘ones with which we have inadequate evolutionary, cultural, or personal experience’
Compare the physical case.
Fast processes are characterised by principles of Impetus mechanics
which yield correct predictions in some unfamiliar* cases, including
point-light displays, and
cartoons
unfamiliar problems (or situations): ‘ones with which we have inadequate evolutionary, cultural, or personal experience’
‘The No Cognitive Miracles Principle:
When we are dealing with unfamiliar* moral problems, we ought to rely less on [...] automatic emotional responses and more on [...] conscious, controlled reasoning, lest we bank on cognitive miracles.’
Greene, 2014 p. 715
unfamiliar* problems = ‘ones with which we have inadequate evolutionary, cultural, or personal experience’
1. Unfamiliarity* depends on inadequacy [by definition]
2. We do not not which evolutionary, cultural, or personal experience is inadequate (unless we know how the faster processes work)
3. Therefore, we do not know which problems are unfamiliar [from 1, 2]
4. Therefore, we can make no practical use of the No Cognitive Miracles Principle [from 3]
wicked learning environments
‘When a person’s past experience is both representative of the situation relevant to the decision and supported by much valid feedback, trust the intuition; when it is not, be careful’
(Hogarth, 2010, p. 343).
action at a distance
weapons of mass destruction (Thomson, 1976)
...
1. Unfamiliarity* depends on inadequacy [by definition]
2. We do not not which evolutionary, cultural, or personal experience is inadequate (unless we know how the faster processes work)
3. Therefore, we do not know which problems are unfamiliar [from 1, 2]
4. Therefore, we can make no practical use of the No Cognitive Miracles Principle [from 3]
‘The recognition model implies two conditions that must be satisfied for an intuitive judgment (recognition) to be genuinely skilled:
First, the environment must provide adequately valid cues to the nature of the situation.
Second, people must have an opportunity to learn the relevant cues.’
(Daniel Kahneman & Klein, 2009, p. 520)
1. Unfamiliarity* depends on inadequacy [by definition]
2. We do not not which evolutionary, cultural, or personal experience is inadequate (unless we know how the faster processes work)
3. Therefore, we do not know which problems are unfamiliar [from 1, 2]
4. Therefore, we can make no practical use of the No Cognitive Miracles Principle [from 3]
fully-informed disagreement about what to do
as a proxy for unfamiliarity
It is true that faster processes are unreliable in unfamiliar* situations.
We do not know which situations are unfamiliar* (unless we know how the faster processes operate).
But we can still make use of the No Cognitive Miracles Principle.
1. Ethical judgements are explained by a dual-process theory, which distinguishes faster from slower processes.
2. Faster processes are unreliable in unfamiliar* situations.
3. Therefore, we should not rely on faster process in unfamiliar* situations.
4. When philosophers rely on not-justified-inferentially premises, they are relying on faster processes.
5. We have reason to suspect that the moral scenarios and principles philosophers consider are unfamiliar situations.
6. Therefore, not-justified-inferentially premises about particular moral scenarios, and debatable principles, cannot be used in ethical arguments where the aim is knowledge.